So, where
does embodied realism stand in this dichotomy? Well, embodied realism is called
realism, and thus it would seem to
fit neatly in this category. And indeed this would be prima facie correct,
since the authors explicitly state their belief that an external world exists. So
then, are we finished here? Well, not exactly. For while the authors will admit
the existence of an objective reality, they deny that there is any neutral
vantage point from which we can know anything about this objective reality
apart from our embodiment:
[C]lassical metaphysical realism cannot be right, since the properties of categories are mediated by the body rather than determined directly by a mind-independent reality. (p. 28)
[Embodied realism] gives up on being able to know things-in-themselves, but, through embodiment, explains how we can have knowledge that, although it is not absolute, is nonetheless sufficient to allow us to function and flourish. (p. 95)
[Embodied realism] denies that we can have objective and absolute knowledge of the world-in-itself…[E]mbodied realism denies on empirical grounds, that there exists one and only one correct description of the world[.] (p. 96)
We will deal
with the inherent problems with these claims in just a moment. Primarily, we
need to observe why they are being
made. This is to ask why the authors are claiming that we cannot have objective
knowledge of reality-in-itself, and why does our embodiment keep us from predicating
properties of reality from a neutral vantage point? The main reason is due to
the levels of embodiment (neural, phenomenological, and cognitive unconscious)
that we surveyed in the first post of this series. Remember that embodied
realism claims that, based on our embodiment, we don’t have a neutral vantage
point to say “X is or isn’t the case,” because things are or are not “the case”
(i.e. real or unreal) relative to our understanding at a certain level of
embodiment. Therefore, we can only say “X is or isn’t the case, at a certain level of embodiment.” So,
what we mean by something being “true” and “real”, on embodied realism, depends
upon the perspective and level of embodiment being considered. To take the
example the authors utilize—and which we saw was false in the first post—color
isn’t “actually” real, if we are attempting to promulgate this statement from a
neutral standpoint. Rather, color is “real” only when considered from the level
of phenomenology, but is it “unreal” when considered from the neural level.
That is, the existence of color is “real” only relative to the perspective,
here the phenomenological level of embodiment, being considered.
Now,
remember that in the aforementioned post we saw these arguments to be false.
Not only can we make absolute predications of reality from a privileged
perspective, but we must do so. In
fact, the author’s own theses contradict their very claims. When they say, for
instance, that we cannot know “things-in-themselves”, or that we cannot have
objective and absolute knowledge of the world, the authors are predicating these propositions as objective
predications of reality from their own privileged vantage point! That is,
they’re saying that it is an objective fact that we cannot know things in
themselves, and it is objectively true that we cannot have objective knowledge.
This is, to say the least, self-refuting. For the embodied realist’s claim that
reality cannot be known is not simply made at the neural level, or the phenomenological
level, or the cognitive unconscious level. No, it’s made from a unique
perspective that says “reality is this
way, period,” even though this is what the embodied realist says cannot be
done. The embodied realist, thus, is blind to the absurd implications of their philosophy. If one level of embodiment cannot be privileged over and above another, then no single proposition can be seen as an adequate predication of reality in any domain whatsoever—since any single proposition can only represent one level of embodiment at a time. But if no single proposition can be an adequate predication of reality in any domain, then the embodied realist’s very claims about objectivity, knowledge, reality, and ontology cannot be adequate predications of reality either, and thus we should pay them no heed.
Furthermore,
if we truly cannot know reality-in-itself, and can have no objective or
absolute knowledge of this reality, then we cannot make those very same claims—i.e.
that we cannot know reality-in-itself and that we cannot have objective
knowledge of the world. That is to say, if we can’t know objective reality,
then the statement “we can’t know objective reality” is also false, since it is
predicated on a knowledge claim about
the nature of reality. Everywhere we turn embodied realism shoots itself in the
foot. This is why, as I said in the last post, embodied realism is junkyard of
poor philosophy.
So, is
embodied realism a misnomer? Should it even be labeled a form of realism? Not
really. While it admits the existence of an external reality, it discards the
proposition that we can have any real knowledge of the objective properties of
this reality, and thus it belongs in the camp of anti-realism.